Human Flourishing: Theology and the Life of Grace
Blackfriars, Oxford - March 2010
Ia
‘Man infinitely surpasses
man’, says Blaise Pascal (Pensées,
434), a thought quoted by Pope Paul VI in his encyclical letter Populorum Progressio (§42), one of the
great church documents on human flourishing. Philosophy has always included a
sense of this, intimations of a transcendence seen at least in those human
activities of thought and choice that make philosophy possible in the first
place. Plato’s eros, for example,
seems to be a force or desire that carries the human being ever onward in a
search for the good, for truth and beauty. A Christianised version of it is well known from Augustine - ‘our hearts are restless’ – so far,
so much agreement – ‘until they rest in you’, Augustine says, identifying the
object of the heart’s quest with God and prefacing his statement with the
reason why this must be the terminus: ‘you have made us for yourself’. As
Sister Maria Boulding’s wonderful translation of the Confessions puts it, ‘you arouse us so that praising you may bring
us joy, because you have made and drawn us to yourself, and our heart is
unquiet until it rests in you’.
Aristotle too sees something
‘divine’ in the knowledge of truth, saying, in Nicomachean Ethics X.7, that the highest exercise of the highest
faculty – the highest flourishing available to us has something god-like about
it:
But
if happiness (eudaimonia) consists in
activity in accordance with virtue (arete),
it is reasonable that it should be activity in accordance with the highest
virtue; and this will be the virtue of the best part of us. Whether then this
be the intellect (nous), or whatever
else it be that is thought to rule and lead us by nature, and to have
cognizance of what is noble and divine, either as being itself also actually
divine (theion) or as being
relatively the divinest part of us (theiotaton),
it is the activity of this part of us in accordance with the virtue proper to
it that will constitute perfect happiness; and it has been stated already that
this activity is the activity of contemplation (theoretike) [1177a12-19; see also 1177b31-34]
Except that it has not been
stated already, at least not in the Nicomachean
Ethics and this text causes perplexity to interpreters of Aristotle for
other reasons also; I mean if they are keen to distance Aristotle from anything
that seems too platonic and to see his real understanding of human flourishing
in the more horizontal, perhaps even secular, accounts of the magnanimous man
living serenely and confidently in the moderate enjoyment of all the good
things life offers.
But the idea that human
flourishing is found in some kind of transcending of limitation continues to be
a concern in many philosophers. This is the argument of Fergus Kerr in his
Stanton Lectures in the Philosophy of Religion, given in 1994-95 and published
as Immortal Longings: Versions of
Transcending Humanity (1997). His aim in those lectures was to focus on the
religion in some recent philosophy, to express dismay at how scant and how poor
is some educated peoples’ knowledge of Christian theology, while seeking to
show how theological preconceptions are nevertheless working in much modern
philosophy. His substantive question – and a version of it can be ours also at
this point in the day – is whether there are ways of acknowledging the
limitations of human existence without regarding these limitations as barriers
on the one hand, and without eliminating our desire to transcend our finitude
on the other. I say ‘a version of
it’ because I don’t suppose it is the case that many people explicitly describe
their desire in this way: ‘I want to transcend my finititude’. It is more
likely that people say ‘I want to be as happy as I can be’, or ‘I want to live
as fruitfully and as joyfully as possible’, or ‘I want to fulfil the potential
of my life’, or ‘I want to live in accordance with what is true about me and my
life’.
Is Pascal’s thought a silly
one, perhaps even a bad one that ought not to be entertained? Would Augustine’s
restless heart not have settled down if he had simply been able to love his
woman and his child, the loves identified by Umberto Eco in Foucault’s Pendulum as the loves in
which a man’s flourishing consists?
Ib
In the opening article of
his Summa theologiae, Aquinas speaks
of human flourishing, salus humana –
human health, wellbeing, salvation, or, we can say, flourishing. This health or
flourishing requires yet one more discipline or teaching, he says, sacra doctrina. This is the case because
the human being is oriented to God as to his goal or end, an orientation that
is beyond the comprehension of the human mind. A human being cannot direct his
intentions and actions to this end unless he has come to know it. So it is
necessary, for human health or flourishing, that these matters be made known
through divine revelation. Aquinas knows there is a part of philosophy called
‘theology’ and that philosophers have presented versions of transcending
humanity, but he is saying that some further knowledge is needed because some
new finality for human aspiration has been revealed.
What can be known about God
otherwise than through this sacra
doctrina – by human reason alone – would only be understood by very few
people, over a long time, and with many distortions. But – he says it for the
third time in a short passage – the entire health or flourishing of humankind (tota hominis salus) depends on knowledge
of this truth which (the knowledge or the truth?) is in God. So that this
health or flourishing might therefore be quickly and certainly accessible to
people, it is necessary that they be instructed about divine things through a
divine revelation.
This introduces us to how
Aquinas understands the science or discipline of sacra doctrina, which from what we know about him we can translate
as ‘sacred teaching’ or as ‘Christian doctrine’. He goes on in that first
question of the Summa theologiae to
propose that this doctrine or teaching – let’s call it ‘theology’ for short –
is a subalternated science, of which there are many examples among the
sciences, an area of research and knowledge which accepts some or all of its
fundamental principles from a superior science and gets on with its business
untroubled by the fact that it cannot itself establish those principles through
itself. The superior science in this case is God’s knowledge of himself and of
all things. This is the science that establishes theology’s first principles, a
science that becomes accessible to us through revelation and faith, theology
then being the systematic investigation of what has become known through
revelation and faith. The point here, from our point of view, is that this is
not just interesting information about things that have nothing crucial to do
with us: this is the truth about the full flourishing of the human being, tota hominis salus (ST I 1,1 in c).
Another word for the
experience in which this flourishing is found is beatitudo, a theme that links all parts of this theological system:
God’s happiness is complete (ST I 26), humans are drawn towards it as their end
(ST I.II 1-5), and their entering into possession of it is made possible by the
incarnation of the Word who showed us in himself the way of truth by which we
may arrive at the full flourishing of eternal life (ST III prologue). In this
Aquinas structures his theology according to one of the first principles
presented to us by revelation: that the Son of God propter nos homines et propter nostram salutem descendit de caelis,
for us, human beings, and for our flourishing. He came that we might have life
and have it abundantly (John 10:10).
So far what have I done?
Well I have reminded us that philosophy has often concerned itself with a human
desire to get beyond what are experienced as negotiable limits to that desire.
And I have reminded us that theology thinks of itself as carrying us further,
though in the same direction. Faith is not ‘reason’s opposite’ as a character
in one of Brian Moore’s novels puts it: faith extends reason’s reach and gives
it more things to think about.
In the second part I want to
speak about a version of transcending humanity we find in Plotinus, known to
Aquinas and considered by him, but not incorporated into Aquinas general
systematic account of human flourishing. I do it as another way of circling
round the same question. At this point, that question has become that of trying
to demonstrate that human flourishing is, in the end, not achieved but
received.
IIa
In that part of his
inaugural lecture that is entitled ‘on the commendation and the division of the
scriptures’, Aquinas appeals to a section of Plotinus’ Enneads (I 2) in support of the view that what Aquinas calls
precepts of wisdom are given to us in the books of Proverbs, Ecclesiastes and
Song of Songs. This is what Aquinas says (he is trying to present a plausible rationale for all the books of the
Bible):
…
these (Proverbs, Ecclesiastes, Song) can be distinguished according to the
three grades of virtue distinguished by Plotinus, since precepts of wisdom
ought to be about nothing else than acts of virtues. In the first level, are
what he (Plotinus) calls political virtues by which a person makes moderate use
of the things of this world and is appropriately involved in social affairs.
The Book of Proverbs is about these virtues. In the second level, are the
‘virtues of the one being purified’ by which a person withdraws himself from
the things of the world out of contempt for them. The Book of Ecclesiastes is
about these virtues: Jerome says Ecclesiastes is geared towards such contempt.
In the third level, are the ‘virtues of the one who is purified’ by which a
person, effectively free of temporal concerns, delights in the contemplation of
wisdom. The Song of Songs is about this (De
commendatione et partitione sacrae scripturae [Marietti, Opuscula Theologica I, §1207).
There are no precepts of
wisdom for Plotinus’ fourth level. This is the level of ‘exemplar virtues’, or
virtues as they exist in God: ‘precepts are not given about such virtues’,
Aquinas says, ‘but are rather derived from them’.
Enneads I 2 is a typical weaving together by Plotinus of
ideas from Plato (the purpose of life is to become godlike) and from Aristotle
(distinguishing moral and intellectual virtues, and being clear that moral
virtues are not found in God). It is known to Aquinas through the writings of
Macrobius who summarised Plotinus’ teaching about these four levels of virtue:
the civic or political virtues (which are the cardinal virtues as normally
understood), exemplar virtues (which are the same qualities at the divine level
with appropriate Aristotelian-informed qualifications), virtues in the process
of purification, and virtues in the achieved state of purification (with the
energy of a Platonic ascent charging an Aristotelian and even Ciceronian
valuing of the active life).
After his appeal to it in
his inaugural lecture, Aquinas speaks of it again in his commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, once where
he discusses whether the cardinal virtues remain in heaven (In III Sent 33, 1,
4 ad 2) and again where he discusses the difference between virtues and gifts
(In III Sent 34, 1, 1 ad 6). In this latter text it is Nicomachean Ethics VII.1 [1145a24] to which he appeals for the
point that divine goodness is something more exalted than virtue.
The plotinian distinction of
levels of virtue is again introduced in Quaestiones
disputatae de Veritate 26,8, this time in a discussion of what passions
were in Christ. In his response Aquinas talks about the difference between
Stoic and Peripatetic understandings of passion. The Stoics were thinking of
Plotinus’ third level, Thomas says, virtues as they are in the purified soul
where passion is not just managed but overcome. The Aristotelians were thinking
of the reasonable management of passions, not their elimination. So the famous
difference between the two schools, as described by Augustine, is a matter of
terminology, Thomas says, rather than a real difference in understanding. For
the purpose of his present argument it is just two levels of Plotinus’ four
that are relevant, the civic or political virtues which he now identifies with
the active life, and the virtues of the purified soul which he identifies with
the contemplative life.
IIb
Aquinas’s most extensive use
of Plotinus’ levels of virtue is in Summa
theologiae I.II 61,5. It comes between the four articles in which he
discusses the cardinal virtues (61, 1-4) and the four articles in which he
discusses the theological virtues (62, 1-4). It might seem then to be a linking
article and the ways in which it is and is not a linking article serve to focus
something crucial about my topic: human flourishing and the life of grace. The
most striking thing here is that Aquinas considers, between the cardinal and
theological virtues, a philosophical version of transcending humanity, one that
weaves together beautifully the teaching of Platonists, Aristotelians and
Stoics, one that is easily adapted to contrasting the active and contemplative
lives, and one that is easily incorporated into a spiritual journey or quest.
Pierre Hadot says that in Neoplatonism ‘the idea of spiritual progress plays a
much more explicit role than in Plato’s writings’ and that ‘the stages of
spiritual progress corresponded to different degrees of virtue’ (Philosophy as a Way of Life: Spiritual
Exercises from Socrates to Foucault, p.99).
In spite of all this,
Plotinus’ does not become Aquinas’ preferred way of speaking about the
fulfilment brought by grace, the possibility for human flourishing opened up by
grace. Instead he speaks of what he calls ‘theological virtue’, of which there
are, he says, three, ‘faith, hope and charity’. These are what Saint Paul had
called ‘the higher gifts’ (1 Corinthians 12:31).
In Summa theologiae I.II 61,5 Aquinas begins his consideration of
Plotinus’ four levels by quoting Augustine who says that the human soul must
aspire to something if virtue is to be born in it. We aspire to God, Augustine
says, and so (Aquinas adds) it is in God that the exemplar of human virtue
pre-exists. So we can speak of God as prudent, temperate, courageous and just:
Thomas says this even though Aristotle says it is ridiculous to use these terms
of God (arg 1 and ad 1). To call them political virtues is in line with
Thomas’s normal understanding of them, as rightly ordering human affairs.
What does he say then about
Plotinus’ other two levels of virtue? Well, even Aristotle agrees that human
beings should draw themselves towards divine things as far as they are able. Nicomachean Ethics X.7 is once again the
place Thomas has in mind, this time the passage in which Aristotle says that
complete human happiness requires a life higher than the human level: ‘not in
virtue of his humanity will a man achieve it, but in virtue of something within
him that is divine … we ought as far as possible to achieve immortality’
[1177b26]. Thus Aristotle, and the scriptures often commend the same thing to
us, Thomas says, for example, ‘you must be perfect as your heavenly Father is
perfect’ (Matthew 5:48). So intermediate virtues are required between the
political virtues, which are simply human, and the exemplar virtues, which are
divine.
Such virtues, Thomas
continues, are distinguished according to movement and rest, the one concerned
with the journey into a likeness to God and the other concerned with the state
of having attained to likeness to God. These are the levels of purifying and
purified virtues, and he describes how the characteristics of prudence,
temperance, fortitude and justice are found at each of these two levels. The
virtues of purified souls are found only in the blessed, and in certain very
perfect people in this life (aliquorum in
hac vita perfectissimorum).
This final article of Summa theologiae I.II 61 throws into
sharper relief the question posed then in the first article of I.II 62: what
then are theological virtues when we have, as the second objection notes,
already spoken about an exemplar or divine level of virtue, the cardinal
virtues as they pre-exist in God? In fact all the objections here express this
view: don’t we know already that man infinitely surpasses man and naturally
aspires to immortality?
Thomas’s response opens a
can of theological worms. Virtue perfects the human being, he says, enabling
him to act in ways that lead to his flourishing. There is, however, a twofold
flourishing or happiness for human beings. One is proportionate to human nature
and is attainable through principles that are natural. The other is a
flourishing that exceeds nature and is attainable only through divine power,
only if we have come to participate in divinity. The Second Letter of Peter
says that through Christ we are made ‘partakers of the divine nature’ (2 Peter
1:4). This requires the addition, Thomas says, of principles or powers by which
a person is oriented to this supernatural flourishing (beatitudo supernaturalis). These principles or powers are called
theological virtues for three reasons: they have God as their object rightly
ordering us to God, they are in us simply from God, and they are available to
us only through divine revelation in sacred scripture.
So he does not simply say
‘yes, there are theological virtues and Plato, Aristotle and Plotinus knew it,
even though all three philosophers give us versions of humanity transcending to
the divine. Human nature itself is transformed, Thomas says, so that these
supernatural virtues are the ‘natural’ activities of that transformed nature.
Plotinus’ divine or exemplar virtues are predicated of God whereas faith, hope
and charity are virtues placed in us by God and towards God.
We thus glimpse grace. There
is much more that could be said and much more that should be said: about the
theological virtues and the gifts of the Spirit, about the new law and the
sacraments, about sanctifying grace, charismatic gifts and particular vocations.
The full human flourishing revealed in Christ does not simply meet our
aspirations towards it. The text of Isaiah to which Thomas had access allows
him to quote the prophet saying ‘without you, no eye can see what you have
prepared for those who love you’ (Summa
theologiae I 1,1 in c [cf Isaiah 64:4 and 1 Corinthians 2:9). Those
aspirations also need to be corrected and redeemed, not simply in order to
extend the reach of intellect and will through faith and hope, but also, and
above all, through charity. Paul’s speech to the philosophers of Athens
recorded in Acts 17 is the first and paradigmatic instance of sacra doctrina and philosophy being
introduced to each other. And it went well, up to a point, and then it broke
down. At what point did it break down? It broke down when Paul began to speak
of the ultimate reality having an interest in us that was more than the desire
to make sport with us. It broke down when Paul said that this ultimate reality
had intervened in human history in one man. And it broke down when Paul said
that that intervention in one man has illuminated the need and poverty of our
situation and shown it to be more conflicted, more pitiable, than we can
realise by ourselves. It broke
down, finally, because Paul called them to conversion: imagine, asking philosophers
to consider changing their minds!
Faith, hope and charity are
not so much then a new level of virtues just like the ones we already know
about as they are a new light and a new life which touches all the earlier
levels. In fact this perspective of theological virtue shows itself most
clearly in the place nearest to us, as our faith and hope in God enable us to
relate to the neighbour, the needy neighbour, as God relates to us. The needy
neighbour’s flourishing requires that we give him food, drink and clothing, his
lack of freedom or lack of health requires that we visit and take care of him,
his strangeness requires that we receive him and his otherness requires that we
be reconciled with each other.
No comments:
Post a Comment